作者gregorsamsa (aphasiac)
看板wisdom
標題Embracing Alienation
時間Sun Sep 1 23:31:40 2024
Symbolic identity
Symbolic identity provides markers of what one is to plaster over the
question of who one is. This obfuscation is not avoidable: there is no
subjectivity without a symbolic identity attached to it. It is impossible to
avoid having an identity. This is what allows us to have a way of relating to
others and of navigating our social situation… Sinking into a symbolic
identity, in contrast, allows one to avoid confronting political questions as
political. These questions appear to have ready-made answers from the
perspective of a symbolic identity. In this sense, symbolic identity is
always an avoidance of the problem of emancipation. This is a point that
Alenka Zupanstresses in What IS Sex? According to Zupan “
(emancipatory) politics begins with ‘loss of identity,’ and there is
nothing deplorable in this loss.” Identity enacts a depoliticization of the
subject. All identity is conformist.
(…The more effort I make to align myself with a symbolic identity, the more
I experience my misalignment with it. This is because the diligence with
which I pursue identification bears witness to its absence, not its presence.
If I really were identical with my identity as a professor, I wouldn’t have
to spend so much time dressing like a professor, talking like a professor,
and walking like a professor.)
Time/space, freedom
As the source of space and time, the subject (as Kant conceives it) cannot
belong spatially or temporally to the world. The world is not, for Kant,
inherently spatial or temporal, since these forms are the contributions that
subjectivity brings to its encounter with externality. After making this
point about space, Kant comes to the same conclusion about time. During this
discussion, he refers to the subject as the basis of the experience of
temporality. According to Kant, “Time is… merely a subjective condition of
our (human) intuition (which is always sensible, i.e., insofar as we are
affected by objects), and in itself, outside the subject, is nothing.
Nonetheless it is necessarily objective in regard to all appearances, thus
also in regard to all things that can come before us in experience.”
Although the form of temporality derives from the subject, it is not
subjective in the sense that one could opt for it or not. It gives our
experience a requisite form that structures it for us, which is why Kant
insists on time as objective rather than merely subjective. But the forms of
space and time also show that the subject is necessarily out of place and out
of time in its existence. Subjectivity can be responsible for temporality
because the subject is not itself subjected to time.
The Kantian subject is its self-division. It is self-conscious because it
relates to itself from a distance rather than just being identical with what
it is. Its self-division manifests itself most significantly in subjectivity’
s relationship to freedom and determination. Rather than theorizing the
subject as either free or determined, Kant insists — and believes that he
proves — that the subject is free and determined at the same time. The point
is not that some of the subject’s actions are free while external causes
determine others but that every action is simultaneously free and determined.
When one considers the subject from a theoretical point of view, it is
determined. But when one thinks of it from a practical standpoint, as a being
in action, it is free. The attempt to discern which of these approaches
accurately apprehends the truth of the subject misses Kant’s point, which is
that both are equally true.
Oppression
…oppression cannot be equivalent to the experience of alienation, since
alienation is universal. Those who are oppressed are not fated to be
alienated subjects with no possibility of overcoming their alienation. The
forces of oppression do not thrust oppressed groups into an unrelenting
alienation. Instead, oppression sets both the oppressing and the oppressed
groups into their symbolic identities, so that everyone has a proper place.
The lure of an oppressive system for the oppressor is that it will provide a
definite social location for everyone, with the illusory promise that no one
will continue to experience alienation. The oppressor and the oppressed
become nothing more than their symbolic identities. The aim of oppression is
to transform all subjectivity into self-identical entity. That said, an
oppressive society is not magically composed of self-identical beings. No one
escapes the divide of alienated subjectivity, not even in the most oppressive
society imaginable. But to be oppressed is to be positioned, pushed into an
identity without a clear path to get out of it. Oppression works to make
self-division invisible even as it relies on this self-division.
Most people know what oppression looks like. It is a social order that
leaves a mass of people in poverty, condemns a certain group to a denigrated
position relative to others, or ostracizes some for who they are. To regard
someone in an oppressive way is to classify the person as a substantial
entity or as a whole. It is to refuse to allow this person to exist as a
divided and contradictory subject with desires that are at odds with
themselves. One does this to create the illusion that both oneself and the
other are self-identical beings.
One indication of the existence of oppression is the reduction of a group to
a collective identity with definite desires or ways of being. In the
oppressed situation, all subjects become reducible to a consistent symbolic
identity. Identity overwhelms subjectivity in the oppressive viewpoint, which
is why people tend to identify those in an oppressed position in a collective
way, with statements such as “They smell bad” or “They are lazy” or even
“They are destroying our nation.” One collectivizes others in this way when
one refuses to recognize them as alienated from themselves and thus
irreducible to any such identity.
…The lure of a stable identity seduces some, but oppression occasions
resistance because alienation is not without its own appeal. Existing as an
alienated subject gives one autonomy from external determinations. Alienation
indicates that one is not identical with any symbolic identity. It signals
that one can act contrary to the expectations inherent in one’s identity.
The fight against oppression is a fight to assert one’s alienation against
the oppressive enforcement of an identity. To strive to embrace one’s
alienated subjectivity is to be engaged in the fight against oppression of
all stripes.
Racism
Racism permits modern subjects to act in ways that violate the moral edicts
that modern philosophy articulates. All the moral philosophers of modernity,
no matter what their specific philosophical stripe, condemn the buying and
selling of people as if they were nothing but material commodities. And yet,
under the spell of racism, slave owners and traders have engaged in this
activity, and most of them have still considered themselves good, moral
people. This is possible because they don’t believe that they are dealing
with subjects when they buy and sell slaves. Racial difference indicates, for
those ensconced in a racist social structure, an absence of subjectivity.
Modernity compels subjects to view all other subjects as their equals, but
the concept of racial difference changes that outlook. The human rights that
modern society espouses count only for those who belong to this society.
Those on the outside don’t count. They are nothing but a symbolic identity
that has no status within the social order.
European racism unevenly distributes the impact of modernity. It allows some
to regard themselves as modern while consigning others to a premodern status.
In The Wretched of the Earth, Frantz Fanon sees the denigration of the racial
other as the underside of modernity. He claims, “This Europe, which never
stopped talking of man, which never stopped proclaiming its sole concern was
man, we now know the price of suffering humanity has paid for every one of
its spiritual victories.” As Fanon points out, the values of modernity don’
t apply to everyone equally. Racism enables those invested in it to see the
racial other as a self-identical being that can be terrorized without
compunction.
Dialectics
Dialectics is the exploration of the contradictions that inhere within every
identity. Whatever seems identical is ultimately revealed, through a
dialectical interpretation, as self-divided and involved in what is other to
it. For Hegel, contradiction is ontological, and alienation is the way that
contradiction manifests itself in the subject. The subject attains freedom
through the alienation that generates and sustains subjectivity. Hegel
pursues a dialectical interpretation of the subject to bring out the
emancipatory power of its alienation.
Realm of freedom
If we could have a realm of freedom distinct and separate from the realm of
necessity, we should go to any lengths to bring this realm about. But if the
realm of freedom always remains embroiled within the realm of necessity, how
we bring it about matters just as much as its eventual emergence, since it
will never fully emerge. Understood in this way, the realm of freedom is not
a future to be achieved but a way of struggling within the realm of
necessity. How we fight matters more than what we accomplish.
The public
In the history of the bourgeois public sphere that Habermas relates, it
develops primarily in privileged spaces, such as coffee houses and salons.
When one enters these spaces, according to Habermas, one retains one’s
private identity while at the same time turning that private identity toward
the public. Private people form a public by advancing their own opinions in a
place where every opinion ideally has an equal weight.
Habermas’s understanding of the public sphere, as important as it clearly
is, undersells both the breadth of the public and the alienation required to
produce it. The public occurs through the encounter between alienated
subjects who turn away from their private concerns to engage with others.
When we are in the public, we are alienated from our private selves. This
alienation is what constitutes a public no matter where it occurs. Through
this shared alienation that distances us from our social positions, we
discover the basis for universal equality. As public, alienated beings, no
one has any more status than anyone else. The recognition of alienation
connects us to everyone else.
The barrier to the recognition of alienation that constitutes the public
is our investment in the idea of community. No one can avoid being part of a
community, just as no one can avoid alienation. But the problem concerns
where our investment lies. When we invest ourselves in a community and in the
symbolic identity that a community provides, we fail to attend to the
alienation that undermines all communal identity. The investment in community
is an investment in having a social place. It is an investment that
obfuscates our displacement and thereby hides the public. To believe that one
belongs to a community is to fail to recognize the universality of
alienation, a universality in which everyone is equal.
A community provides a larger context in which the subject is not simply
alone with itself but has others to provide support for its identity. As a
form, a community promises belonging, no matter what its size or what its
specific content. It never delivers on this promise, however, which is why
the public emerges. Community seems secure, and the public seems dangerous.
But community and the public exist in a dialectical relation: the public
exists through the community’s failure to fully constitute itself. There is
a public because there is no self-identical community. Further, there is
community because no one can exist purely in a state of alienated
subjectivity.
Community
All community depends on at least one particular being excluded. In this
sense, every community is a gated community, no matter how open and welcoming
it appears. Rather than being an oxymoron as some critics label it — “If it
’s gated, it’s not really a community” — the gated community has a
paradigmatic status relative to all other communities. Communities form
through keeping people out. If they fail to do this, if they are open to
everyone, they cease to be communities and become public. It is impossible to
conceive of a community that avoids the act of exclusion.
--
※ 發信站: 批踢踢實業坊(ptt.cc), 來自: 36.236.99.237 (臺灣)
※ 文章網址: https://webptt.com/m.aspx?n=bbs/wisdom/M.1725204705.A.3B0.html